General conception of the Nature of Ratiocination
A judgment is the comparison of a subject or thing with a predicate or attribute . The comparison is made by using the copula or linking verb is or its negative is not. Therefore, a judgment is a declarative sentence, which is a categorical proposition. Example: The tiger is four-footed. A predicate can also have its own predicate. In the example, the predicate four-footed can, itself, have the further predicate animal. One of these predicates is immediately and directly connected to the subject or thing. The other predicate is mediate and indirectly connected to the subject.
The tiger ----------is---------- a four-footed---------- animal.
In order to have clear knowledge of the relation between a predicate and a subject, I can consider a predicate to be a mediate predicate. Between this mediate predicate or attribute, I can place an intermediate predicate. For example, in the judgment the sun is luminous, I attempt a clarification by inserting the predicate star, which then becomes an immediate predicate, intermediate between the subject sun and the mediate predicate luminous.
The sun is a star that is luminous.
Sun = subject
Is = copula
Star = immediate predicate
Luminous = remote mediate predicate
Kant calls this process ratiocination. It is the comparison of a remote, mediate predicate with a subject through the use of an intermediate predicate. The intermediate predicate is called the middle term of a rational inference. The comparison of a subject with a remote, mediate predicate occurs through three judgments:
Luminous is a predicate of star;
Star is a predicate of sun;
Luminous is a predicate of sun .
This can be stated as an affirmative ratiocination: Every star is luminous; the sun is a star; consequently the sun is luminous.
Note: Kants examples utilized obscure subjects such a Soul, Spirit, and God and their supposed predicates. These do not facilitate easy comprehension because these subjects are not encountered in everyday experience and consequently their predicates are not evident.
Section II - Of the Supreme Rules of all Ratiocination
Kant declared that the primary, universal rule of all affirmative ratiocination is: A predicate of a predicate is a predicate of the subject .
The primary, universal rule of all negative ratiocination is: Whatever is inconsistent with the predicate of a subject is inconsistent with the subject.
Because proof is possible only through ratiocination, these rules cant be proved. Such a proof would assume the truth of these rules and would therefore be circular. However, it can be shown that these rules are the primary, universal rules of all ratiocination. This can be done by showing that other rules, that were thought to be primary, are based on these rules.
The dictum de omni is the highest principle of affirmative syllogisms. It says: Whatever is universally affirmed of a concept is also affirmed of everything contained under it. This is grounded on the rule of affirmative ratiocination. A concept that contains other concepts has been abstracted from them and is a predicate. Whatever belongs to this concept is a predicate of other predicates and therefore a predicate of the subject.
The dictum de nullo says: Whatever is denied of a concept is also denied of everything that is contained under it. The concept is a predicate that has been abstracted from the concepts that are contained under it. Whatever is inconsistent with this concept is inconsistent with the subject and therefore also with the predicates of the subject. This is based on the rule of negative ratiocination.
Section III - Of Pure and Mixed Ratiocination
If one judgment can be immediately discerned from another judgment without the use of a middle term, then the inference is not a ratiocination. A direct, non-ratiocinative inference would, for example, be: from the proposition that all airplanes have wings, it immediately follows that whatever has no wings is not an airplane.
Pure ratiocination occurs by means of three propositions. Mixed ratiocination occurs by more than three propositions. A mixed ratiocination is still a single ratiocination. It is not compound, that is, consisting of several ratiocinations.
An example of a mixed ratiocination is:
Nothing immortal is a man,
Therefore, no man is immortal;
Socrates is a man,
Therefore, Socrates is not immortal.
A mixed ratiocination interposes an immediate inference, resulting in more than three propositions. However, a mixed ratiocination may show only three propositions if the fourth proposition is unspoken, unexpressed, and merely thought. For example, the ratiocination
Nothing immortal is a man,
Socrates is a man,
Therefore, Socrates is not immortal is only valid if the fourth proposition Therefore, no man is immortal is covertly thought. This unspoken proposition should be inserted after the first proposition and is merely its negative converse.
Section IV
In the so-called First Figure only Pure Ratiocinations are possible, in the remaining Figures only mixed Ratiocinations are possible.
Pattern of First Figure:
Subject...............Predicate
Middle Term........Major Term........Major Premise
Minor Term.........Middle Term........Minor Premise
Minor Term........Major Term...........Conclusion
A ratiocination is always in the first figure when it accords with the first rule of ratiocination: A predicate B of a predicate C of a subject A is a predicate of the subject A. This is a pure ratiocination. It has three propositions:
C has the predicate B,
A has the predicate C,
Therefore, A has the predicate B.
In the Second Figure only mixed Ratiocinations are possible.
Pattern of Second Figure:
Subject...............Predicate
Major Term........Middle Term........Major Premise
Minor Term.........Middle Term........Minor Premise
Minor Term........Major Term...........Conclusion
The rule of the second figure is: Whatever is inconsistent with the predicate of a subject is inconsistent with the subject. This is a mixed ratiocination because an unexpressed proposition must be added in thought in order to arrive at the conclusion. If I say,
No B is C,
A is C,
Therefore, A is not B
My inference is valid only if I silently interpose the immediate inference No C is B after the first premise. It is merely the negative converse of the first premise. Without it, the ratiocination is invalid.
In the Third Figure only mixed Ratiocinations are possible.
不科学!美国21年后击败中国 奥数夺冠
沃尔玛全资收购一号店
自动美甲机:喷涂秒速完成
不作死就不会死 13个欠揍的文学角色
希腊议会通过改革方案
日本婚庆新热潮:羊驼当证婚人狂受追捧
白金汉宫展览揭秘女王国宴
老外考中国驾照 连考四次才通过
靠谱吗?NASA宣布发现“另一个地球”
松鼠借酒消愁 发酒疯被扔出酒吧
盛夏来临 当心“情绪中暑”
用Apple Pay花钱是何样体验
牛津词典告诉你 英语里一共有多少单词!
魔兽世界电影导演专访:赞吴彦祖帅遍全球
中国富人不好做 富人不再如从前
结婚越晚离婚越快?!
英文神还原《三字经》
印度亚洲公路1号线今何在
NASA发现新“宜居带”
考眼力:图中的雪豹在哪儿?
中行拟在亚洲扩大业务
华为智能手机营收大幅增长
香港初创企业开发蜗居生态链
揭秘韩剧何以在中国大受欢迎
澳洲土豪金黄金厕纸每卷卖800万
珍珠奶茶的珍珠是用什么做的?
外媒看中国:华为科技引爆全球热卖
研究:吸电子烟也会上瘾
中国出资设立基金以减少全球贫困
微软上一财季净亏32亿美元
不限 |
英语教案 |
英语课件 |
英语试题 |
不限 |
不限 |
上册 |
下册 |
不限 |