General conception of the Nature of Ratiocination
A judgment is the comparison of a subject or thing with a predicate or attribute . The comparison is made by using the copula or linking verb is or its negative is not. Therefore, a judgment is a declarative sentence, which is a categorical proposition. Example: The tiger is four-footed. A predicate can also have its own predicate. In the example, the predicate four-footed can, itself, have the further predicate animal. One of these predicates is immediately and directly connected to the subject or thing. The other predicate is mediate and indirectly connected to the subject.
The tiger ----------is---------- a four-footed---------- animal.
In order to have clear knowledge of the relation between a predicate and a subject, I can consider a predicate to be a mediate predicate. Between this mediate predicate or attribute, I can place an intermediate predicate. For example, in the judgment the sun is luminous, I attempt a clarification by inserting the predicate star, which then becomes an immediate predicate, intermediate between the subject sun and the mediate predicate luminous.
The sun is a star that is luminous.
Sun = subject
Is = copula
Star = immediate predicate
Luminous = remote mediate predicate
Kant calls this process ratiocination. It is the comparison of a remote, mediate predicate with a subject through the use of an intermediate predicate. The intermediate predicate is called the middle term of a rational inference. The comparison of a subject with a remote, mediate predicate occurs through three judgments:
Luminous is a predicate of star;
Star is a predicate of sun;
Luminous is a predicate of sun .
This can be stated as an affirmative ratiocination: Every star is luminous; the sun is a star; consequently the sun is luminous.
Note: Kants examples utilized obscure subjects such a Soul, Spirit, and God and their supposed predicates. These do not facilitate easy comprehension because these subjects are not encountered in everyday experience and consequently their predicates are not evident.
Section II - Of the Supreme Rules of all Ratiocination
Kant declared that the primary, universal rule of all affirmative ratiocination is: A predicate of a predicate is a predicate of the subject .
The primary, universal rule of all negative ratiocination is: Whatever is inconsistent with the predicate of a subject is inconsistent with the subject.
Because proof is possible only through ratiocination, these rules cant be proved. Such a proof would assume the truth of these rules and would therefore be circular. However, it can be shown that these rules are the primary, universal rules of all ratiocination. This can be done by showing that other rules, that were thought to be primary, are based on these rules.
The dictum de omni is the highest principle of affirmative syllogisms. It says: Whatever is universally affirmed of a concept is also affirmed of everything contained under it. This is grounded on the rule of affirmative ratiocination. A concept that contains other concepts has been abstracted from them and is a predicate. Whatever belongs to this concept is a predicate of other predicates and therefore a predicate of the subject.
The dictum de nullo says: Whatever is denied of a concept is also denied of everything that is contained under it. The concept is a predicate that has been abstracted from the concepts that are contained under it. Whatever is inconsistent with this concept is inconsistent with the subject and therefore also with the predicates of the subject. This is based on the rule of negative ratiocination.
Section III - Of Pure and Mixed Ratiocination
If one judgment can be immediately discerned from another judgment without the use of a middle term, then the inference is not a ratiocination. A direct, non-ratiocinative inference would, for example, be: from the proposition that all airplanes have wings, it immediately follows that whatever has no wings is not an airplane.
Pure ratiocination occurs by means of three propositions. Mixed ratiocination occurs by more than three propositions. A mixed ratiocination is still a single ratiocination. It is not compound, that is, consisting of several ratiocinations.
An example of a mixed ratiocination is:
Nothing immortal is a man,
Therefore, no man is immortal;
Socrates is a man,
Therefore, Socrates is not immortal.
A mixed ratiocination interposes an immediate inference, resulting in more than three propositions. However, a mixed ratiocination may show only three propositions if the fourth proposition is unspoken, unexpressed, and merely thought. For example, the ratiocination
Nothing immortal is a man,
Socrates is a man,
Therefore, Socrates is not immortal is only valid if the fourth proposition Therefore, no man is immortal is covertly thought. This unspoken proposition should be inserted after the first proposition and is merely its negative converse.
Section IV
In the so-called First Figure only Pure Ratiocinations are possible, in the remaining Figures only mixed Ratiocinations are possible.
Pattern of First Figure:
Subject...............Predicate
Middle Term........Major Term........Major Premise
Minor Term.........Middle Term........Minor Premise
Minor Term........Major Term...........Conclusion
A ratiocination is always in the first figure when it accords with the first rule of ratiocination: A predicate B of a predicate C of a subject A is a predicate of the subject A. This is a pure ratiocination. It has three propositions:
C has the predicate B,
A has the predicate C,
Therefore, A has the predicate B.
In the Second Figure only mixed Ratiocinations are possible.
Pattern of Second Figure:
Subject...............Predicate
Major Term........Middle Term........Major Premise
Minor Term.........Middle Term........Minor Premise
Minor Term........Major Term...........Conclusion
The rule of the second figure is: Whatever is inconsistent with the predicate of a subject is inconsistent with the subject. This is a mixed ratiocination because an unexpressed proposition must be added in thought in order to arrive at the conclusion. If I say,
No B is C,
A is C,
Therefore, A is not B
My inference is valid only if I silently interpose the immediate inference No C is B after the first premise. It is merely the negative converse of the first premise. Without it, the ratiocination is invalid.
In the Third Figure only mixed Ratiocinations are possible.
译林版八年级上册英语Test for Unit 5学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 7单元测评同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Six Period Six学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 4单元测评同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Seven Period Four学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 5同步训练同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Six Period Five学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Eight Period Three学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Seven Period One学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Test for Unit 7学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Five Period Five学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Seven Period Two学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Seven Period Three学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 1同步训练同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Six Period Three学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Test for Unit 4学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 3单元测评同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Seven Period Six学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 6同步训练同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Five Period One学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Eight Period Four学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Eight Period Five学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语Unit 2单元测评同步解析与测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Four Period Three学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Five Period Two学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Mid-term test学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Eight Period Two学习与评价答案
人教版九年级上册英语同步解析与测评Unit 5单元测评答案
译林版八年级上册英语Unit Four Period Four学习与评价答案
译林版八年级上册英语Final test学习与评价答案
不限 |
英语教案 |
英语课件 |
英语试题 |
不限 |
不限 |
上册 |
下册 |
不限 |